Note: A much shorter version of this essay is due to appear in the Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1999 Mainz (Trier: WVT, 2000).
Abstract -- According to Stanley Fish, narratology is an
ill-conceived theoretical project that can never succeed.
Narratologists generally reciprocate by marking Fish down as
counterproductive or by pointedly ignoring what he is saying. The
present essay argues that both sides are wrong. Assuming that
much is to be learned from Fish's denunciation of theory, it will
trace the development of his philosophy of reading from the
late-structuralist program of "affective stylistics" to his
current position of radical relativism constrained only by the
norms and values of "interpretive communities." Specifically, it
will discuss Fish's test cases concerning ambiguity,
situatedness, fact, and truth, and make an attempt to reorient
his insights within the wider contexts of cognitive linguistics,
pragmatics, and artificial intelligence. In conclusion, the essay
argues that both Fish's insights and his oversights significantly
impact on many branches of what has come to be termed
"postclassical" narratology.
1. Ambiguity
Although the keyword is unaccountably missing from the indexes
of Is There a Text in This Class (Fish 1980) and Doing
What Comes Naturally (Fish 1989), Fish's oeuvre is full of
references to ambiguity, and a compulsive indexer could
profitably arrange them under subdescriptors such as "in
literature," "in natural language," "in puns," "local," "global,"
"illocutionary," "pervasiveness of," etc. Ambiguity, as Fish
recalls (1980, 56-58), came into the focus of critical interest
in the 1930s when publication of William Empson's Seven Types
of Ambiguity started what might be described as the first
school of dedicated ambiguity hunting. At the time, Empson's
strategy of finding rather than of resolving ambiguities fed into
the New Critics' program of demonstrating the richness of (mainly
poetical) texts, not -- as is the custom today -- of disclosing
the faultlines at which they fissure and fall apart. Empson
eventually asserted that "all good poetry" was ambiguous (1949,
xv), elevating ambiguity to a criterial feature that prefigured
today's notion of literary polyvalence. Paradoxically, while
Empson's brilliant textual analyses were widely accepted as the
cutting edge of the discipline, the "seven types" themselves were
fuzzy to the point of uselessness, as Fish notes (1980, 57).
Consider, for instance, the mess Empson makes of type number
four:
An ambiguity of the fourth type occurs when two or more meanings of a statement do not agree among themselves, but combine to make clear a more complicated state of mind in the author. Evidently this is a vague enough definition which would cover much of the third type, and almost everything in the types which follow . . . . (1949, 133)Actually, Fish's critique is leveled not so much at Empson's definitions (though these are surely "vague enough") but at the fact that he approaches his subject from a mixture of heterogeneous points of view -- cohesion, intention, and reading effects, in the above quote. Fish himself, in contrast, begins his own project of a "Literature in the Reader" (1980, ch. 1) by addressing small-scale and volatile ambiguities that Empson did not even consider worthy of name, let alone type. Consider the following almost unnoticeable ambiguity from Paradise Lost:
Satan, now first inflamed with rage came down,
The Tempter ere th' Accuser of man-kind,
To wreck on innocent frail man his loss
Of that first battle, and his flight to Hell.
(qtd Fish 1980, 3)
At issue, here, is the referent of "his" in lines 11 and 12 (=
3 and 4 in quote). Globally speaking, this is clearly Satan. Yet,
Fish says, if one carefully traces one's steps and surveys the
state of affairs as it presents itself at the end of line 11,
"his" is evidently strongly attracted to the immediately
preceding "man." It is only the wider context of line 12 and its
allusion to the person in question's "flight to Hell" that the
connection between "his" and "man" dissolves in favor of one
between "his" and Satan. Naturally, Fish seizes on the
opportunity to point out that it is an aesthetically and morally
relevant fact that the passage momentarily tempts the reader to
confuse man with Satan.
For many critics, the foregoing analysis will not present
too compelling a case, first because Fish's reconstruction of the
reading process is handled a bit too glibly,1 second,
because the ambiguity lasts only the briefest of moments, and
third, because many readers will simply deny that they were ever
tempted to make that false connection. Evidently, Fish's point
is better served by local ambiguities that introduce more
palpable textual difficulties. As a matter of fact, Fish manages
to unearth a very convincing item from an early 17C sermon by
Lancelot Andrewes:
He is found of them that seeke Him
not
but
of them that seeke Him
never
but found (qtd. Fish 1980, 184)
The structural ambiguities suffusing this passage do not resolve
as easily here as in the Milton example. Indeed, a number of
trial-and-error moves are needed to arrive at a reading that
makes overall sense, and an impatient reader may easily give up.
Ultimately, after following up and duly backtracking on a number
of wrong turns, the globally consistent (correct? intended?)
reading worked out by Fish is that lines 1-2 constitute a sense
unit presenting a statement about people who find God even though
they do not seek Him, while the rest of the passage asserts that
people who do seek Him are certain to succeed (He . . .
is never but found = He is always found). Although this reading
resolves the textual difficulty, it is as anticlimactic as a
finished puzzle, and Fish's point is precisely that the passage
is valuable not for the message that it ultimately conveys but
for the mental exercise that it affords as one labors over it.
As Fish points out, recognition of this fact slips through the
net of a globalizing formalist approach because "the only making
of sense in a formalist reading is the last one, whereas
everything a reader does, even if he later undoes it, is part of
the 'meaning experience' and should not be discarded" (1980,
3-4).
The counterpart of local ambiguity is persistent
ambiguity, the only "true" kind of ambiguity in the view of many
commentators. As Fish shows, discussing the concluding lines of
Milton's sonnet 20, persistent ambiguity comes with its own set
of processing effects:
He who of these delights can judge, and spare
To interpose them oft, is not unwise. (qtd Fish 1980,
148)
"Spare" has two likely, but contradictory, meanings ('leave time
for' and 'refrain from') which cannot be easily accommodated in
the ordinary naturalizations available for cases such as this,
namely as paradoxes or puns. As Fish points out, Milton exegetes
usually follow the impulse to resolve the ambiguity by looking
for disambiguating evidence in the wider context -- the context
of Milton's sonnets, Milton's works, Milton's "known attitudes,"
and so on. What happens, however, is that consideration of higher
levels of context merely leads to an infinite regress of
alternate confirmations and disconfirmations. Fish himself
concludes from what he thinks is an "equal availability of both
interpretations" (1980, 151) that Milton's text conveys,
precisely, a "blurred judgment." Making his methodological point,
Fish states that this type of semiosis is inaccessible to
"formalist criticism," which assumes that "meanings can be
specified independently of the activity of reading" (1980, 152).
Specifically, the formalist approach reduces ambiguities like
Milton's "spare" either to "an (insoluble) crux" or eliminates
them "in the course of a procedure that is incapable of finding
value in temporal phenomena" (1980, 155).
In linguistics, context is usually defined as the text
surrounding an item, ambiguous or otherwise. The conventional
formal notation is W__Z, where W and Z denote preceding (left)
and subsequent (right) contexts, respectively. More generally,
the extralinguistic situation in which an utterance is embedded
is also usually called "context".2 While situational
context is a (more or less) holistic construct, the only verbal
context available at any one point in time during processing is
previous context, i.e., W__. Specifically, Charles Hockett showed
that a textual segment that begins with the phrase A man
eating fish is locally ambiguous because it may refer either
to a piscivorous man or to a hominivorous fish. If the text
continues ... on Friday is not necessarily a Catholic then
the first reading is strongly confirmed; if the text continues
called the piranha is found in the tropical waters of
Brazil the second reading is confirmed; and if it continues
has an unbalanced diet then neither reading is confirmed
and further disambiguating evidence is called for (Hockett 1961,
226).
Hockett's speculative excursions into a "grammar for the
hearer" (1961) and a "grammar of silence" (1967, ch. 7.4) were
counterproposals to what he fittingly labeled "marble slab
grammars." As Hockett put it, the traditional grammarian
regards
a sentence as an enduring structure, to be scanned at leisure and repeatedly, and as easily from right to left or upside-down or inside-out as from left to right. He can do this because he deals not directly with a sentence, but only with a representation thereof, spread out before him like a cadaver on a marble slab, to be dissected at his convenience. (Hockett 1961, 220)Today, Hockett's deliberations are justly considered seminal prolegomena toward a project of cognitive linguistics that materializes and acquires momentum in the sixties. One of the questions that has been investigated since is whether and to what extent comprehension processes use any wait-and-see strategies (van Dijk and Kintsch 1983, 66). As Hockett (1961, 221) suspected, all present evidence indicates that readers do not suspend parsing of a sentence until they have heard or read all of it. On the contrary, resting content with the flimsiest of evidence, readings are usually construed as early and quickly as possible. Naturally, given such readerly strategies, there is a certain risk of being occasionally wrong. Being occasionally wrong in turn requires compensatory strategies of undoing prior readings and following up untried options. Processing mechanisms such as these are typically highlighted by "garden path" constructions which trap the reader in a processing failure from which it is difficult to recover. The standard example, invented by Thomas G. Bever (1970, 316), is The horse raced past the barn fell [= the horse that was raced past the barn fell]. Fish, in his discussion of local ambiguities in Milton and Andrewes, is the first critic to unearth instances of literary garden paths which are not just temporary readerly errors but have a specific (writerly?) functionality. The garden-path phenomenon has since become a favorite testing ground in psycholinguistics and artificial intelligence research. Significantly, it can also be observed in minimal stories like jokes and riddles as well as in more complex narratives like short stories and novels (see Jahn 1998 for a survey).
narrowly defined, almost every utterance is ambiguous. In fact, almost every utterance is multiply ambiguous, with possible semantic interactions among its individual ambiguous constructions. . . . It is thus quite typical for an utterance to have dozens, or even hundreds, of possible propositional interpretations. However, speaker and hearer are normally able to select a single one of these interpretations without even realizing that they have made a choice. It is generally agreed that this choice is a function of the context; but to define the function, as opposed to claiming that it exists, is no easy task. (Sperber and Wilson 1981, 298)As one can see, Mey takes a "product-oriented" view that assumes that true ambiguity is rare and of little ultimate consequence in everyday communication, whereas Sperber and Wilson take a "process-oriented" view claiming not only that ambiguity is rampant but that disambiguation is an essential part of meaning construction. It is this latter view of process-oriented, pervasive ambiguity that Fish embraces; indeed, for Fish, univocity is so unreal that ambiguity lacks the true opposite that would render it distinctive: "to label a sentence 'ambiguous' will be to distinguish it only if there are sentences that always and only mean one thing, and I would contend that there are no such sentences" (1980, 281). Thus, when E. D. Hirsch suggests that The air is crisp is unambiguous, Fish points out that the sentence does not in fact disambiguate the word air ('local atmospheric condition'/'melody') (Fish 1980, 309). Similarly, when linguists argue that The suit is too light [in color or in weight?] to wear is conclusively disambiguated when placed in a context like __ on such a cold day, Fish shows that such seemingly disambiguating contexts are themselves prone to becoming reinterpreted in wider contexts (1980, 281).
Consider the small example of the utterance "Can you pass the salt?" immediately construed by the vast majority of native speakers as a request for performance of a specific action rather than as a question about the hearer's physical abilities; but this is so because in the very hearing of the utterance we assume the mealtime setting populated by agents concerned with eating and drinking" . . . . If one varies the setting and reconceives it as a conversation between a doctor and a patient recovering from surgery, the utterance "Can you pass the salt" could indeed be heard as a question about the hearer's physical ability . . . . Independently of some such already assumed context (and there could be many more than two), the utterance wouldn't have any meaning at all and wouldn't be an utterance, but merely a succession of noises or marks. . . . In the example of "Can you pass the salt?" it is always possible that someone at a dinner table may hear the question as one about his abilities, or that a patient may hear his doctor asking him to pass the salt (perhaps as a preliminary to an experiment). (1989, 295-6).Fish makes four important points here. First, he shows that Can you pass the salt? is illocutionary ambiguous because it has a literal and an indirect-speech-act reading. Second, he offers an explanation of why the indirect-speech-act reading is the normally preferred one (because, he says, the mealtime setting is the "standard story"). Third, he demonstrates that choice of reading freely varies with context. And fourth, he has the wonderful acuity to recognize that the only context that really counts is what the hearer assumes to be relevant. In exactly the same vein, Sperber and Wilson (1986, ch. 3.3) compellingly argue that context is not what is objectively given but what is actively chosen by understanders. Ultimately, Fish says, context is "a product of interpretation and as such is itself variable as a constraint" (1989, 108).
2. Shaping eyes and nontrivial machines
Even as he recognizes that context is subjective and "variable
as a constraint," Fish does not for a moment doubt that its
import extends far beyond the management of ambiguity. Context
determines meaning, changes meaning and creates meaning out of
meaninglessness. Specifically, in order to demonstrate that
context is also a major factor in the assessment of truth, Fish
picks up a test case first presented by John Austin:
In the penultimate chapter of How To Do Things with Words, J. L. Austin presents a sentence and asks us to consider it. The sentence is "France is hexagonal," and the question he puts to it is a very familiar one in analytical philosophy: Is it true or false? The answer, however, is not so familiar. It depends, says Austin: "I can see what you mean by saying that it is true for certain intents and purposes. It is good enough for a top-ranking general, perhaps, but not for a geographer" (p. 142). I[n] other words, the truth or falsehood of a sentence is a function of the circumstances within which it is uttered, and since it is always uttered within some set of circumstances or others, it is not in and of itself either true or false, accurate or inaccurate, precise or imprecise. (Fish 1980, 197)Truth or falsehood, Fish says here, is a function of circumstances -- deviating slightly from Austin, whose "final answer" is that the sentence is a "rough description" and therefore neither true nor false (1962, 142). In addition, while ostensibly supporting Austin's vision of studying "not the sentence but the issuing of an utterance in a situation" (qtd Fish 1980, 231; orig. Austin 1962, 138), Fish recognizes that (just as in the case of Can you pass the salt?) it is not the situation per se that is relevant -- a mealtime setting, a general glancing at a sketch of France, a cartographer in converse with other cartographers, in short, any kind of reality seen objectively -- but the construction of the (or a) situation in the mind of the speaker or hearer passing the true-or-false judgment. Austin himself takes a step toward context-in-the-mind by granting that something can be "true for certain intents and purposes," "true for a general," etc. Fish soon makes the radical generalization that "what is normal (like what is ordinary, literal, everyday) is a function [Fish's italics] of circumstances in that it depends on the expectations and assumptions that happen to be in force" (1980, 287).
My students did not proceed from the noting of distinguishing features to the recognition that they were confronted by a poem: rather, it was the act of recognition that came first -- they knew in advance that they were dealing with a poem -- and the distinguishing features then followed. . . . As soon as my students were aware that that it was poetry they were seeing, they began to look with poetry-seeing eyes, that is, with eyes that saw everything in relation to the properties they knew poems to possess. . . . It was almost as if they were following a recipe -- if it's a poem do this, if it's a poem, see it that way -- and indeed definitions of poetry are recipes, for by directing readers as to what to look for in a poem, they instruct them in ways of looking that will produce what they expect to see. . . . Skilled reading is usually thought to be a matter of discerning what is there, but if the example of my students can be generalized, it is a matter of how to produce what can thereafter be said to be there. Interpretation is not the art of construing but the art of constructing. Interpreters do not decode poems: they make them. (1980, 326-7)Emphasizing, in his conclusion, that "Interpretation is . . . the art of constructing," Fish is only a figura etymologica away from "constructivism," a set of influential epistemological axioms accumulating from the works of Giambattista Vico, Immanuel Kant, Wilhelm von Humboldt, William James, Charles Sanders Peirce, Edward Sapir, and Benjamin Lee Whorf (among the more recent prophets of "radical" constructivism one usually includes Humberto Maturana, Heinz von Foerster, Paul Watzlawik, Siegfried J. Schmidt, and Francisco J. Varela). On his private journey toward constructivism, Fish starts out by establishing that the original "assignment reading" of the Buffalo text is in no respect more accurate than, or logically prior to, the poetic reading that is projected on it by his poetry students. In fact, seeing the text as a list of names is just as dependent on interpretive strategies as seeing it as a poem is. Evidently, Fish feels that the outcome of the experiment is indicative not only of understanding of texts but also of "acts of recognition" and of "thinking, seeing, reading" in general (1980, 335). Humans (like all living organisms, presumably) have a "shaping eye" (1980, 333) that has no other way of seeing than to see x (a real object) as y (a percept). Specifically, Fish adds, seeing x as y is a function of a mind's culturally acquired beliefs and interpretive operations.
Fig. 1. Trivial and nontrivial machines (von Foerster 1993,
357-59).
According to von Foerster, a trivial machine is one that always
produces the same results, no matter how often or in what
sequence values of x are fed into it, and no matter what
operation f1 performs. The interesting thing here is that there
are tasks that trivial machines do extremely well and others
where they are wholly useless. For instance, while a trivial
machine easily outperforms a human in tasks like squaring
numbers, searching a text for a word, or watering the plants, it
is highly unlikely that it will ever plausibly disambiguate a
sentence or be able to judge whether it is true or false. Even
though cognitive judgments are often so spontaneous as to seem
"automatic," artificial intelligence theorists have come to
recognize (a) that basic cognitive processes are extremely hard
to monitor, and (b) that a computational language processor has
no choice but to closely mimic human cognitive processes. In
other words, there can be no understanding outside human
understanding, and human understanding, as all of Fish's test
cases amply show, is neither abstract nor ahistorical nor
generally consistent.
Intriguingly, von Foerster's nontrivial machine does present
a design that has access to a memory of situations and the
capacity to modify its states in accordance with what it is
doing. Superficially, a nontrivial machine is not much different
from a trivial machine; in fact, both are indistinguishable from
the outside. Like a trivial machine, a nontrivial machine gets
input data x, performs some function or process f2, and produces
output y. The crucial differences are in internal design and
behavior: in addition to acting on input x, f2 also gets input
from the machine's current internal state (the box labeled S);
and S is in turn affected (changed) by the outcome of f2's
operation. Two consequences follow: like humans, nontrivial
machines are historically conditioned (they learn, they forget,
they change), and they are difficult to predict. For
illustration, consider one trivial and three not-so-trivial
examples.
a) Suppose we are observing the input-output behavior of a
machine whose interior design and program is hidden from us in
a black box. During a period of time we note the following six
input-output pairs:
... M-m, x-X, G-g, d-D, P-p, C-c, ...Apparently, the machine uses a function that turns upper-case letters into lower-case letters and vice versa. One can fairly confidently predict that if fed another "M" it will produce an "m", if fed an "e" it will produce an "E", and so on. Since output is both predictable and unaffected by temporal sequence it seems safe to assume that the machine's black box houses a trivial machine.
b) Suppose we observe another black box that generates the
following sequence:
... A-a, B-b, A-b, A-b, B-a, B-b, ...All that it seems safe to say here is that input consists exclusively of upper-case A's and B's while output consists exclusively of lower-case a's and b's. Otherwise it is hard to explain what goes on, or to predict what the output is going to be if the machine were fed another A or B. As a matter of fact, output can be described as the product of a nontrivial machine that uses four rules and interacts with two internal states (states 1 and 2):
(i) If x = "A" and S = 1, then produce y = "a" and leave machine in S = 1.
(ii) If x = "A" and S = 2 then produce y = "b" and leave machine in S = 2.
(iii) If x = "B" and S = 1 then produce y = "b" and put machine into S = 2.
(iv) If x = "B" and S = 2 then produce y = "a" and put machine into S = 1.The reader will be relieved to learn that this particular nontrivial machine was constructed before presenting the input-output sequence. The reverse task, that is, deducing a nontrivial machine from its input-output data is often impossible (von Foerster 1993, 359).
c) Consider the familiar "Necker cube" reproduced in Fig. 2.
The cube is ambiguous: it can either be seen from right and above
or from left and below. In perception, disambiguation is so
instantaneous that many people doubt that it ever took place.
After a while, that is, after continuing exposure to the same
input, a "spontaneous" reversal takes place, and the cube is
suddenly seen in its alternate orientation. Although one can
consciously stick to one interpretation for a while, once
attention flags, uncontrollable point of view switches follow.
The reasons for the reversal effect are largely unknown. Even if
the viewer is aware of the fact that the figure is ambiguous its
two aspects are never seen simultaneously.5
d) Suppose there are four major mind states or "life positions"
informing the psychological structure of human beings: (1) I'm
OK, you're OK, (2) I'm OK, you're not OK, (3) I'm not OK, you're
OK, (4) I'm not OK, you're not OK (Harris 1967, ch. 3). Suppose
person A meets person B and is greeted with x = "And how are you
this fine morning?" Consider what A may make of x, and what s/he
might reply, given any of the four states s/he could be in.
Further, consider how A's interpretation of x might modify or
confirm his/her current state.
One of the major advantages of models like those in Fig. 1
is that they allow the researcher to focus on constitutive
elements and to stake out specific fields of inquiry without
losing sight of crucial relations or the general picture.
Methodologically, the model suggests "structured" strategies such
as top-down design, modularity, and stepwise refinement. While
f2, S, and their interfaces are open to design and
trial-and-error testing, constructivists generally agree that
perceptual input is just "a pattern of stimulations" (Churchland
1993, 46), or, as Fish puts it, a mere "succession of noises and
marks" (Fish 1989, 296). As Fish's Buffalo experiment shows, even
formal features (lines of verse vs. a list of names) have no
objective reality independent of interpretation. As regards
components S and f2 in von Foerster's nontrivial machine, Fish's
descriptive vocabulary actually provides a number of useful
conceptualizations. Specifically, S may be the dynamic store of
a mind's "assumptions" (1980, vii), "convictions," "beliefs"
(1980, 199), "expectations" (1980, 277), "tacit knowledge" (1980,
330), "interests and goals" (1980, 332), "values and norms"
(1980, 334), while f2 may be taken to contain a mind's
"interpretive program," "recipe," collection of "routines" (1995,
41), "constitutive rules" (1980, 241), etc.
Evidently, there is a remarkable degree of convergence
between Fish's notion of shaping eyes, the pragmalinguists'
conception of chosen context, the constructivists' model of
nontrivial machines, and the artificial intelligence programmers'
project of designing a computational natural language processor.
Regrettably, this is just an incidental agreement rather than the
product of a genuine meeting of minds, theories, and disciplines.
In fact, after arguing the constructivist axioms, Fish assumes
an "anti-foundationalist" position that negates much of the
interdisciplinary promise that has been so obvious in this
section.
3. Interpretive Communities
Just as a person's shaping eyes see reality not for what it
really is but for what it is made out to be on the basis of
beliefs and interpretive strategies, texts are not read for what
they really are but for what readers make of them. For
many critics, including Fish, allowing texts to be "written" by
readers raises the specter of interpretive anarchy (1980, 172).
The moment Fish opens the Pandora's box of subjective relativism,
however, he slams it to and seals it shut by making all
individual judgment dependent on community conventions.
In this new vision both texts and readers lose the independence that would be necessary for either of them to claim the honour of being the source of interpretive authority; both are absorbed by the interpretive community which, because it is responsible for all acts interpreters can possibly perform, is finally responsible for the texts those performances bring into the world. (1989, 142).Fish's turn of the screw ostensibly produces a function of a function -- he begins by establishing that a person's perception is a function of interpretive strategies, and now he establishes that interpretive strategies are functions of community perspectives. Further characteristics of interpretive communities follow readily: two readers who share the same beliefs and strategies belong to the same interpretive community. Members of the same interpretive community will "agree" (1980, 169) about what "counts as a fact, of what is central, peripheral, and worthy of being noticed" (1980, 337); "and conversely, members of different communities will disagree because from each of their respective positions the other 'simply' cannot see what is obviously and inescapably there" (1980, 15). Depending on the behavior of their populations, interpretive communities "grow larger and decline, and individuals move from one to another," and "ways of interpreting . . . can . . . be forgotten or supplanted, or complicated or dropped from favor ('no one reads that way any more')" (1980, 171-2). Over and above the members that constitute it, an interpretive community is defined not by a "closed set of rules" (1989, 151) but by an adaptive and self-regulating code (1989, 150) of assumptions that tends to change over time: "neither interpretive communities nor the minds of community members are stable and fixed, but are, rather, . . . engines of change . . . whose work is at the same time assimilative and self-transforming" (1989, 152). (Interpretive communities, one is tempted to say, behave like non-trivial machines.)
What I was trying to persuade them [the formalists] from was not a fundamental or natural way but a way no less conventional than mine . . . This meant that the business of criticism was not (as I had previously thought) to determine a correct way of reading but to determine from which of a number of possible perspectives reading will proceed. (1980, 16)Leaving no doubt about what is at issue, Fish states that "no interpretation can be said to be better or worse than any other, and in the classroom this means that we have no answer to the student who says my interpretation is as valid as yours" (1980, 317). But Fish also immediately assures us that there is no cause for alarm. "Total and debilitating relativism," he argues, cannot arise because all readings are always sanctioned by the interpretive community for and in which they are made. Because community restrictions are always in force, the "brakes" against subjective interpretations and idiosyncratic meanings (1980, 338) "are always on" (1989, 83). Obviously, too, the fact that different interpretive communities license different readings does not entail that a text can be read as anything. The question "What Makes an Interpretation Acceptable" (1980, ch. 15) can always be asked, and always be answered, positively or negatively, with reference to community conventions. Since there are many interpretive communities, however, no reading, not even seemingly "absurd or impossible" ones (1980, 342-345; 1989, 104-107, 193), can be ruled out on the strength of some set of absolute constraints. While it is hard to imagine that anyone would seriously claim that Hamlet is a forceful man of action (1989, 107), that Agatha Christie's novels are treatises on death, or that Blake's "Tyger" is a "prophetic message inspired by Aunt Tilley" (1980, 343), one cannot simply say that the line has to be drawn somewhere. "If someone says that King Lear is a little girl he is wrong," emeritus Cambridge (UK) Professor Derek Brewer has recently stated in an attempt to call (post)modern critics to order, and to shore up a minimal consensus no longer, notably, about what is right but about what is wrong (Brewer 1994, 44). Assuming a characteristic attitude of contrariousness, Fish makes it a point to demonstrate that absurd interpretations such as the foregoing have a habit of acquiring a sufficient measure of acceptability as soon as they are situated in an appropriate context. For instance, the Aunt-Tilley reading of Blake's "Tyger" becomes as good as unassailable within the community of reader-response critics who allow elicitation strategies such as free association. "No reading," Fish states categorically, "however outlandish it might appear, is inherently an impossible one" (1980, 347).
Molly points out specifically that her charged position within constructs of both motherhood and racialism at the time Bloom met her -- a young, sexual Jewess tending her dying mother -- was partly what drew him to her. ("I suppose on account of my being a Jewess looking after my mother" [18.1184]). (Doyle 1994, 133)Joyceans are generally aware of the fact that very few nouns in Molly's monologue are capitalized and may take the trouble to check the original, just in case. The line quoted by Doyle actually reads:
we stood staring at one another as if we met somewhere I suppose on account of my being jewess looking after my mother (18.1183)Minute as the differences may seem, Doyle's reading misconstrues and her rewriting distorts the text. Not only does Doyle illegitimately capitalize "jewess," projecting her own focus of interest, she also inserts a phantom indefinite article. Molly isn't "a" Jewess looking after her mother, but Jewess-looking, after her mother, the way her mother did. There is no known indication in Ulysses (the authoritative account being Raleigh's Chronicle of Leopold and Molly Bloom) that Molly's mother was dying when Molly met Bloom, or that she is dead in 1904, or that Molly tended her, or that Molly's father, Major Tweedy, is Jewish. In fact, what textual evidence there is favors Molly's Catholicism -- she remembers going to confession, and plans to buy "a bit of fish tomorrow or today is it Friday" (18.939). While none of this is conclusive -- a woman eating fish on Friday isn't necessarily a Catholic -- it certainly makes it problematic to proceed on the notion that Molly is Jewish. As it stands, Doyle's case is instructive for two reasons: on the one hand it supports Fish's assumption that the critic's shaping eye sees what it sees according to an interpretive community's decision about what "is worthy of being noticed" (in this case, the race thematic); on the other hand it throws into question his reassurance that a "text cannot be overwhelmed by an irresponsible reader and one need not worry about protecting the purity of a text" (1980, 336). There is, after all, a larger principle that says that erring is human, suggesting that Fish's rule no reading is an inherently impossible one must be supplemented by a corollary to the effect that mistaken readings are not inherently impossible, either.
4. Anti-foundationalism and anti-theory
In section 2 of this essay I drew attention to the fact that
there is a remarkable convergence between the tenets of Fish's
philosophy and those of constructivism. Yet rather than embrace
constructivism in proper fashion, Fish prefers to turn to
anti-foundationalism, the "going argument" (1989, 345),
he claims, in philosophy, history, sociology, hermeneutics,
history of art, legal theory, and literary theory.
Anti-foundationalism, in Fish's definition, "teaches that
questions of fact, truth, correctness, validity, and clarity can
neither be posed nor answered in reference to some
extracontextual, ahistorical, nonsituational reality, or rule,
or law, or value" (1989, 344). But, properly understood,
anti-foundationalism also removes any "ground" on which to base
a theory in the first place. No theoretical undertaking, Fish
says, can change or guide the beliefs and interpretive strategies
that the members of an interpretive community are already using
in their everyday practice (of "seeing, thinking, reading")
without the assistance of theory. So, even before a
Fishian constructivist literary studies program (or whatever one
might call it) can work up a stride, Fish's anti-theoretical
stance radically alienates him from constructivists, literary
theorists, and narratologists alike. As Culler complains as early
as 1981,
It is not a little ironic that a man who has so imperiously thrust the reader before us, announced a new age of criticism focussed on the reader, and insisted that meaning and value lie not in the text itself but in the activity of reading, should then turn and tell us that we need not enquire what that activity involves. Indeed, it is not ironic but bathetic. (Culler 1981, 126)Nevertheless, Fish's argument against theory does deserve closer attention. Appropriately enough, Fish begins by deliberating the question of "what theory is and is not" (1989, 315). Picking up E. D. Hirsch's distinction between "rules" and "rules of thumb," Fish explains that
A rule is formalizable: it can be programmed on a computer and, therefore, can be followed by anyone who has been equipped with explicit (noncircular) definitions and equally explicit directions for carrying out a procedure. A rule of thumb, by contrast, cannot be formalized, because the conditions of its application vary with the contextual circumstances of an ongoing practice. (1989, 317)According to Fish, strict (programmable, formalizable) rules have their place in mathematics and linguistics, while rules of thumb underlie behavioral patterns, legal scenarios, and games -- roughly, they are strategies "to try if you want to succeed in the game" (1989, 316). Theory, in Fish's view, is definitionally predicated on strict rules, while any description that invokes rules of thumb merely reflects "the contingent practices of particular communities" (1989, 320). Since every so-called fact is historically and culturally situated, it can, at best, fall under rules of thumb, not abstract or strict rules. For this reason (though in singularly ill-chosen phrasing), "every rule is a rule of thumb" (1989, 321), meaning, presumably, every rule of interest to Fish. Theory, in contrast, amounts to imagining a "theoretical machine" that, flawlessly and consistently, produces some "desired result":
In linguistics, that result would be the assigning of correct descriptions to sentences; in literary studies the result would be the assigning of valid interpretations to works of literature. In both cases (and in any other that could be imagined) the practitioner gives himself over to the theoretical machine, surrenders his judgment to it, in order to reach conclusions that in no way depend on his education, or point of view, or cultural situation. (1989, 319)Apart from the image of minds dominated by machines (which is always greatly effective), the rational part of Fish's argument is notably fragile. To begin with, it is oddly ahistorical (for Fish, of all people) to reduce theory to the programmability of its rules -- evidently, theories existed before the advent of computers. Second, if theory by definition excluded strategic and context-sensitive rules then there could be no such thing as "game theory" -- yet computers can play a mean game of chess, and it is not the end of civilization as we know it (well perhaps it is, for master chess players). Third, the rules of "preferences" (Jackendoff 1987), "fuzzy logic" (McNeill and Freiberger 1993), and "neural nets" (Churchland 1993) that are the order of the day for today's "intelligent" computational algorithms are ostensibly closer in nature to rules of thumbs than to strict rules. Fourth, the only type of "theoretical machine" Fish can think of is a trivial machine, a design now generally granted to be unsuited for capturing essential and basic human cognitive abilities. Interestingly, "being right" and "yielding correct results" (1989, 316) for today's computational natural language processors means going wrong on items like garden path sentences. A computational parser that cracks The horse raced past the barn fell without batting an eye is not worth the paper it has been designed on -- the trick is to design it in such a manner that it falls for the trap just like ordinary people do (Fodor and Inoue 1994). The reason for this is obvious: the cognitive mechanisms that trigger the garden path effect are precisely those that allow effective and effortless comprehension of ordinary sentences in the first place.
Theories are usually introduced when previous study of a class of phenomena has revealed a system of uniformities that can be expressed in the form of empirical laws. Theories then seek to explain those regularities and generally, to afford a deeper and more accurate understanding of the phenomena in question. To this end, a theory construes those phenomena as manifestations of entities and processes that lie beyond or beneath them, as it were. These are assumed to be governed by characteristic theoretical laws, or theoretical principles, by means of which the theory then explains the empirical uniformities that have been previously discovered, and usually also predicts "new" regularities of similar kinds. (Hempel 1966, 70)Unlike Fish, Hempel requires his laws to be specifiable "with appropriate clarity and precision" (Hempel 1966, 71), a far shot from requiring them to be formalizable and programmable. Hempel is also not at all concerned about the fact that a theory can make do with whatever rules are at hand. Mathematically precise rules are fine, presumably, but if all the rules available turn out to be rules of thumb then that is apparently fine, too, without the project losing the name of theory.
I am not saying that [Ruth] Kempson is beyond criticism simply because the context of which she is an extension prevents her from seeing certain arguments as respectable or even makable. In my very strong opinion the arguments she clings to, the arguments that underwrite the project of formal linguistics, are wrong. And it is part of my argument that I can say that despite the sympathetic analysis I make of her "epistemological condition." This does not mean that I am not in the same condition -- embedded in conviction -- but that precisely because I am embedded in conviction, my sense of the rightness of my arguments is no less strong than hers and is in no way diminished by my ability to give an account of its source. (1989, 3)The question here is how Fish's "sense of rightness," which allows him to see Kempson's approach as "wrong," can be "in no way diminished" by his "ability to give an account of its source" -- when at the bottom of this account is the anti-foundationalist insight that there is no once-and-for-all truth, and the conviction that a statement "is not in and of itself either true or false" (1980, 197). The fact of the matter is, Fish wants to have it both ways. When he feels like it, he describes divergent or contradictory readings as naturally issuing from the beliefs and strategies of interpretive communities and contends that "the business of criticism [is] not . . . to determine a correct way of reading but to determine from which of a number of possible perspectives reading will proceed" (1980, 16). To his credit, he can take that same stance of aloofness in questions where his own interests and convictions are concerned, in Milton studies, for instance. When the mood hits him, however -- and this usually happens when an article of anti-foundationalist faith itself is at issue -- he will stand on his convictions about what is true or false, right or wrong, and can adamantly declare that an approach like Kempson's is plainly "wrong." Inevitably, at this point, the classical law of contradiction rears its ugly head and declares that, situatedness or no situatedness, let constructivists and anti-foundationalists say what they will, something cannot be both true and false.
I intend it [the title] to refer to the unreflective actions that follow from being embedded in a context of practice. This kind of action -- and in my argument there is no other -- is anything but natural in the sense of proceeding independently of historical and social formations; but once those formations are in place (and they always are), what you think to do will not be calculated in relation to a higher law or an overarching theory but will issue from you as naturally as breathing. (1989, ix)If all actions are "unreflective" then awareness dwindles into insignificance regardless of the fact that, as Fish takes pains to point out, it is ever-present. "[O]ne is always aware, one always knows what one is doing, and, when challenged, one can always give reasons," Fish says (1989, 462). "To be in a situation," Fish adds, "(as one always is) is already to be equipped with an awareness of possible goals, obstacles, goals, dangers, rewards, alternatives, etc." (1989, 466). And yet the only conclusion Fish draws from this is that there is no point in raising a call for becoming aware (as critical theorists do). Ultimately, Fish thinks, both theoretical reflection and judgments based on "analytical and critical attention" can be safely ignored as immaterial to the practice of perception and action.
5. Fish's contribution to postclassical narratology
Everything Fish says against literary theory in general also
applies to narratology in particular. Narratology, he claims, is
a "paradigm instance of theory in the strong sense" mustering
"formidable apparatuses" (1989, 567n2) and strict rules to
formulate general laws that disregard what happens when the
practitioner-critic "makes" a valid interpretation -- processes
that, he believes he has shown, are inaccessible to abstract
theoretical analysis. True enough, according to Todorov,
narratology's main goal is "no longer the description of the
particular work, the designation of its meaning, but the
establishment of general laws of which this particular text is
the product" (1981, 6-7). Todorov also defined narratology as "a
science of narrative" (1969, 10), an epithet that many literary
critics reared in French and Anglo-American humanities
departments found somewhat unsettling. As Seymour Chatman,
himself a first-generation narratologist, commented in 1990,
'Narratology' is a word that Henry James would have deplored, though he might have found merit in its objects of concern. After twenty years, I still feel something of an ironic twinge when I see it in print. A "science" of narrative seems an unlikely, even a slightly shady pursuit. But, of course, "-ology" can also mean "theory of," and who, these days, would dare fault theory?" (Chatman 1990, 1)Well, Fish does, for one, and lest it be forgot, he is by no means the only one to do so.7
Most of the features isolated above, and indeed most of the
postclassical narratological branches mentioned above, can be
accommodated within the framework of a "natural" narratology as
proposed by Fludernik (1996). Summed up very briefly, Fludernik's
model exploits real-world cognitive frames and scripts --
specifically, schemata of experiencing, telling, and reflecting
-- as units of theoretical description (1996, ch. 1.3). According
to this approach, there is a prototypical narrative situation of
conversational storytelling which provides a default frame for
concepts like narrative communication, story and discourse,
narrators and focalizers, pragmatic contracts, tellability
conventions, good form, good performance, and so on. At this
level of naturalization, the narrator unabashedly "speaks," the
narrative "represents" a fictional world, the mimetic illusion
overrides constructivist skepticism, and characters exist as
pragmatically and psychologically real beings. Situatedness, in
this model, locates the narrator in a discourse here-and-now, the
recipient in a reception here-and-now (in the audience, in front
of the text), and the reflector in the story here-and-now (due
allowance has to be made for the wider senses of "story" and
"discourse" alluded to above). A special set of standard
deviations from these primary orientations is exemplified by what
Bühler (1965) called "transpositions to the Phantasma," that
is, shifts to second or third level deictic coordinates. For
instance, reflectors may phase out to or return from daydreams
or recollections, while narrators may imaginatively transpose to
the story here-and-now (description, hypothetical focalization,
Herman 1994), or adopt a reflector's view of events
(reflector-mode narrative, "delegated" focalization). Readers,
in turn, may imaginatively hear the narrator speak and adopt (or
possibly distance themselves from) the narrator's point of
view.
Despite its reliance on real-life schemata of
"experientiality" (Fludernik 1996, 28-30), natural narratology
ultimately rests on a level of constructivist metareflection
which views all natural frames and scripts, including those
related to the narratological toolbox itself, not as
representative of signifieds in a world out there but as
interpretive strategies generating Peircean interpretants. Here
is an example of how, in Fludernik's model, traditional
narratological categories acquire their constructivist
underpinnings:
[O]ne can now comprehend Stanzel's narrative situations as a direct development from natural categories. Fiction with a teller figure evokes situational real-life equivalents of telling and their characteristic constellations. If there is a personalized narrator, for example, a certain cognitive, ideological, linguistic and sometimes even spatio-temporal position may become attributed to that narrator, and she becomes a 'speaker' on the model of the standard communication script. One can thereby explain the entire communicative analysis of fiction as an (illicit) transfer of the frame of real-life conversational narrative onto literary personae and constructed entities. (1996, 47)Apart from the "constructed entities" mentioned in the last line of the quote, the true constructivist watchword in this passage is "illicit." Like Fish, the natural narratologist wants to eat the cake of natural frames, and at the same time exercise the option to view them from a skeptical distance. But while Fish's account founders in paradox and incoherence, natural narratology maps out a heterogeneous belief space that protects its cognitive frames under an overarching constructivist purview.
Conclusion
What role can Fish play in postclassical narratology? The easy
answer to this is, None. Fish himself would refuse to lend his
name to the narratological project, no matter whether it styles
itself classical or postclassical, and the notion of an
anti-foundationalist narratology is a contradiction in terms.
Moreover, reviewing Fish's argument from a narratological
vantage, one must acknowledge that there are lasting and
unbridgeable disagreements, especially concerning the feasibility
of theory, the structure of consciousness, and the status of
unreflective actions. Yet apart from these areas of disagreement,
it is remarkable how fittingly Fish's philosophy of reading ties
in with current narratological concerns, and how well it paves
the road to a fruitful exchange of concepts and models with
disciplines such as pragmatics, cognitive linguistics, and
artificial intelligence. So perhaps the question should be
rephrased. If one cannot let Fish have the last word, would it
be feasible to allow him the first?
This time the answer is Yes. There is no-one, to begin with,
who argues the case for constructivism better than Fish does
(even if, ultimately, he does not wholly embrace it himself). It
is no disadvantage, either, that Fish is a jargon-free writer who
can be as lucid as John Austin and as relentlessly probing as
Ludwig Wittgenstein. Even his occasional bouts of casuistry can
be excused as springing from a laudable rhetoric of "telling you,
by way of examples" (1989, 159). Opening up the literary
dimension of a field that is growing like a tree (or, some
critics would say, like a disease), Fish instructs the reader in
constructivist conceptions of mental contexts, situatedness, the
nature of truth, fact, and reality, and interpretive communities.
Hopefully, the reader will also learn from Fish's errors -- his
proposal to abolish theory, his attempt to argue self-conscious
awareness out of existence, and his fractalist model of
consciousness. Owing him this -- the lessons of his insights and
the lessons of his oversights -- the least the reader can do is
drink him a toast. To Stanley Fish: he opened the window and in
flew Enza.9
Notes
1. One question is whether the reading process is actually
open to this type of retrospective inspection. As Culler points
out (1981, 130), it is also not clear whether Fish's account
captures both an expert's and a general reader's reading
experience.
2. More technically, the distinction is one between
co-text (verbal context) and context (situational
context). The point made here is that the holistic formula W__Z
applies to situational but not to verbal context.
3. Consider Socrates has eight letters (Searle 1974,
73) -- true, false, or undecideable?
4. Deviating slightly from von Foerster (1993), Fig. 1 uses
a simplified version of the nontrivial machine model.
5. See Jackendoff (1987, 116) on the perception of ambiguous
visual and linguistic data, and Jahn (1997) for a discussion of
literary analogues.
6. See Bode (1996) for an extended discussion of Fish's
argument against the possibility (or effectiveness) of theory and
self-conscious awareness.
7. See especially Knapp and Michaels (1982) and Parrinder
(1987). Instructively, Knapp and Michaels exempt narratology from
their attack against theory because it is "essentially empirical"
and has "no direct bearing on the interpretation of individual
works" (1982, 11) -- a view few narratologists today would be
prepared to accept.
8. The current interest in cognitive matters is also
evidenced by an MLA-hosted discussion group on "Cognitive
Approaches to Literature." See web site
humanitas.ucsb.edu/users/steen/Culture/ for details.
9. The pun comes from "A Litter to Mr. James Joyce" by
"Vladimir Dixon" (Our Exagmination Round his Factification for
Incamination of Work in Progress, ed. Sylvia Beach, New York:
New Directions, 1962, p. 193).
References
Adams, Jon-K. 1996. Narrative Explanation: A Pragmatic Theory
of Discourse. Frankfurt: Lang.
Austin, John L. 1962. How to Do Things with Words, edited
by J. O. Urmson. Oxford: Clarendon.
Baars, Bernard J. 1997. In the Theater of Consciousness.
Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
Bal, Mieke. 1983. "The Narrating and the Focalizing: A Theory of
the Agents in Narrative." Style 17: 234-69.
---. 1985. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of
Narrative. Translated by Christine van Boheemen. Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.
Banfield, Ann. 1982. Unspeakable Sentences: Narration and
Representation in the Language of Fiction. London:
Routledge.
Barthes, Roland. 1975 [1966]. "An Introduction to the Structural
Analysis of Narrative." New Literary History 6:
237-72.
Beaugrande, Robert de. 1983. "Surprised by Syncretism: Cognition
and Literary Criticism Exemplified by E. D. Hirsch, Stanley Fish,
and J. Hillis Miller." Poetics 12: 83-137.
Berne, Victor. 1973. What do You Say After You Say Hello.
New York: Bantam.
Bever, Thomas G. 1970. "The Cognitive Basis For Linguistic
Structures." In Cognition and the Development of Language,
edited by John R. Hayes, 279-361. London: Wiley.
Bickerton, Derek. 1995. Language and Human Behavior.
Seattle: Univ. of Washington Press.
Bode, Christoph. 1996. "Why Theory Matters." In Why Literature
Matters: Theories and Functions of Literature, edited by
Rüdiger Ahrens and Laurenz Volkmann, 87-100. Heidelberg:
Winter.
Brewer, Derek. 1994. "Abuses of English Studies." The European
English Messenger 3.2: 40-46.
Bühler, Karl. 1965 [1934]. Sprachtheorie: Die
Darstellungsfunktion der Sprache. 2nd ed. Stuttgart: G.
Fischer.
Chatman, Seymour. 1969. "New Ways of Analyzing Narrative
Structure with an Example from Joyce's Dubliners."
Language and Style 2: 3-36.
---. 1978. Story and Discourse: Narrative Structure in Fiction
and Film. London: Cornell Univ. Press.
---. 1986. "Characters and Narrators: Filter, Centre, Slant, and
Interest-Focus." Poetics Today 7: 189-204.
---. 1990. Coming to Terms: The Rhetoric of Narrative in
Fiction and Film. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press.
Cohn, Dorrit. 1978. Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for
Presenting Consciousness in Fiction. Princeton: Princeton
Univ. Press.
---. 1990. "Signposts of Fictionality: A Narratological
Perspective." Poetics Today 11: 775-804.
Churchland, Paul M. 1993. "On the Problem of Truth and the
Immensity of Conceptual Space." In Realism and
Representation, edited by George Levine, 44-69. Madison:
Univ. of Wisconsin Press.
Colomb, Gregory G. and Mark Turner. 1989. "Computers, Literary
Theory, and Theory of Meaning." In The Future of Literary
Theory, edited by Ralph Cohen, 386-410. London:
Routledge.
Culler, Jonathan. 1975. Structuralist Poetics: Structuralism,
Linguistics and the Study of Literature. London:
Routledge.
---. 1980. "Fabula and Sjuzhet in the Analysis of Narrative."
Poetics Today 1: 27-37.
---. 1981. "Stanley Fish and the Righting of the Reader." The
Pursuit of Signs: Semiotics, Literature, Deconstruction.
Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press. 119-131.
Dennett, Daniel C. 1988. "Why everyone is a novelist." Times
Literary Supplement September 16-22: 1016-1028.
Dijk, Teun A. van and Walter Kintsch. 1983. Strategies of
Discourse Comprehension. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Doyle, Laura. 1994. Bordering on the Body: The Racial Matrix
of Modern Fiction and Culture. Oxford: Oxford Univ.
Press.
Duchan, Judith F., Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, eds.
1995. Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science
Perspective. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.
Empson, William. 1949. Seven Types of Ambiguity. London:
Chatto & Windus.
Fish, Stanley. 1980. Is There a Text in This Class? The
Authority of Interpretive Communities. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard Univ. Press.
---. 1989. Doing What Comes Naturally: Change, Rhetoric, and
the Practice of Theory in Literary and Legal Studies. Oxford:
Clarendon.
---. 1995. Professional Correctness: Literary Studies and
Political Change. Oxford: Clarendon.
Fludernik, Monika. 1993. The Fictions of Language and the
Languages of Fiction: the Linguistic Representation of Speech and
Consciousness. London: Routledge.
---. 1996. Towards a 'Natural' Narratology. London:
Routledge.
Fodor, Janet Dean and Atsu Inoue. 1994. "The Diagnosis and Cure
of Garden Paths." Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 23:
407-34.
Foerster, Heinz von. 1993. "Mit den Augen des anderen." In
Wissen und Gewissen, edited by Siegfried J. Schmidt,
350-63. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Genette, G‚rard. 1980 [1972]. Narrative Discourse.
Translated by Jane E. Lewin. Oxford: Blackwell.
---. 1988 [1983]. Narrative Discourse Revisited.
Translated by Jane E. Lewin. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press.
Glowinski, Michal. 1977. "On the Fist-Person Novel." New
Literary Histotry 9: 103-114.
Gove, Philip B. 1966. "Self-explanatory Words." American
Speech 41: 192-98.
Hamburger, Käte. 1977 [1957]. Die Logik der Dichtung.
3rd ed. Stuttgart: Klett.
Harris, Thomas A. 1967. I'm OK -- You're OK. London:
Pan.
Hempel, Carl G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science.
Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Herman, David. 1994. "Hypothetical Focalization."
Narrative 2: 230-53.
---. 1999. "Introduction: Towards a Post-classical Narratology."
In Narratologies: New Perspectives on Narrative Analysis,
edited by David Herman. Ohio: Ohio State Univ. Press.
Herring, Henry D. 1998. "Constructivist Narratology."
Hockett, Charles F. 1961. "Grammar for the Hearer." In
Structure of Language and its Mathematical Aspects,
220-36. Providence: American Mathematical Society.
---. 1967. Language, Mathematics, and Linguistics. Paris:
Mouton.
Hutcheon, Linda. 1988. A Poetics of Postmodernism: History,
Theory, Fiction. London: Routledge.
Iser, Wolfgang. 1978. The Act of Reading: A Theory of
Aersthetic Response. Baltomore: Johns Hopkins Univ.
Press.
Jackendoff, Ray. 1987. Consciousness and the Computational
Mind. London: M.I.T. Press.
---. 1997. The Architecture of the Language Faculty.
Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press.
Jahn, Manfred. 1997. "Frames, Preferences, and the Reading of
Third-Person Narratives: Towards a Cognitive Narratology."
Poetics Today 18: 441-68.
---. 1998. "Package deals, Exklusionen, Randzonen: das
Phänomen der Unverläßlichkeit in den
Erzählsituationen." In Unreliable Narration: Studien zur
Theorie und Praxis unglaubwürdigen Erzählens in der
englischsprachigen Erzählliteratur, edited by Ansgar
Nünning, 81-106. Trier: WVT.
---. 1999. "'Speak, friend, and enter': Garden Paths and their
Narratological Implications." In Narratologies: New
Perspectives on Narrative Analysis edited by David Herman,
000-000. Ohio: Ohio State Univ. Press.
Joyce, James. Ulysses. A Critical and Synoptic Edition,
edited by Hans Walter Gabler. New York: Garland, 1986.
Johnson-Laird, Philip N. 1981. "Mental Models of Meaning." In
Elements of Discourse Understanding, edited by Aravind K.
Joshi, Bonnie L. Webber, and Ivan A. Sag, 106-26. Cambridge:
Cambridge Univ. Press.
Knapp, Steven and Walter Benn Michaels. 1982. "Against Theory."
In Against Theory: Literary Studies and the New
Pragmatism, edited by W. J. T. Mitchell, 11-30. Chicago:
Univ. of Chicago Press.
Lanser, Susan Sniader. 1981. The Narrative Act: Point of View
in Prose Fiction. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
---. 1992. Fictions of Authority: Women Writers and Narrative
Voice. London: Cornell Univ. Press.
Lehnert, Wendy G. 1979. "The Role of Scripts in Understanding."
In Frame Conceptions and Text Understanding, edited by
Dieter Metzing, 79-95. Berlin: de Gruyter.
McClary, Susan. 1997. "The Impromptu That Trod on a Loaf: Or How
Music Tells Stories." Narrative 5: 20-35.
McNeill, Daniel and Paul Freiberger. 1993. Fuzzy Logic.
New York: Simon & Schuster.
Mey, Jacob L. 1993. Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Mezei, Kathy, ed. 1996. Ambiguous Discourse: Feminist
Narratology and British Women Writers. Chapel Hill: Univ. of
North Carolina Press.
Minsky, Marvin. 1979 [1975]. "A Framework for Representing
Knowledge." In Frame Conceptions and Text Understanding,
edited by Dieter Metzing, 1-25. New York: de Gruyter.
Morris, Charles. 1964. Signification and Significance: A Study
in the Relations of Signs and Values. Cambridge, Mass.:
M.I.T. Press.
Nünning, Ansgar. 1990. "Bausteine einer konstruktivistischen
Erzähltheorie: die erzählerische Umsetzung
konstruktivistischer Konzepte in den Romanen von John Fowles."
Delfin 7.1: 3-17.
---. 1992. "Mimesis und Poiesis im englischen Roman des 18.
Jahrhunderts: Überlegungen zum Zusammenhang zwischen
narrativer Form und Wirklichkeitserfahrung." In Neue Lesarten,
neue Wirklichkeiten: Zur Wiederentdeckung des 18.
Jahrhunderts, edited by Gerd Stratmann and Manfred
Buschmeier, 46-69. Trier: Wissenschaftlicher Verlag.
---. 1999. "On the Perspective Structure of Narrative Texts:
Steps towards a Constructivist Narratology." Papers of the 1997
Utrecht conference, edited by Seymour Chatman and Will van
Peer.
Parrinder, Patrick. 1987. The Failure of Theory: Essays on
Criticism and Contemporaray Fiction. Brighton: Harvester.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1965. Principles of Philosophy.
Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap.
Perry, Menakhem. 1979. "Literary Dynamics: How the Order of a
Text Creates Its Meaning." Poetics Today 1-2: 35-64;
311-361.
Prince, Gerald. 1982. Narratology: The Form and Functioning
of Narrative. New York: Mouton.
Raleigh, John Henry. 1977. The Chronicle of Leopold and Molly
Bloom. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.
Ricoeur, Paul. 1984-1988. Time and Narrative. Three
Volumes. Translated by Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer.
Chicago: Chicago Univ. Press.
---. 1991. "Life in Quest of Narrative." On Paul Ricoeur:
Narrative and Interpretation, edited by David Wood. London:
Routledge. 20-33.
Ronen, Ruth. 1994. Possible Worlds in Literary Theory.
Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Ryan, Marie-Laure. 1981. "The Pragmatics of Personal and
Impersonal Fiction." Poetics 10: 517-539.
---. 1991. Possible Worlds, Artificial Intelligence, and
Narrative Theory. Bloomington: Univ. of Bloomington &
Indianapolis Press.
Schank, Roger C., 1995. Tell Me a Story: Narrative and
Intelligence. Evanston: Northwestern Univ. Press.
---, and Robert P. Abelson. 1977. Scripts, Plans, Goals and
Understanding: an Inquiry into Human Knowledge. Hillsdale,
N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Schmidt, Siegfried J. 1989. "Past: Notes on Memory and
Narration." Empirical Studies of the Arts 7: 191-203.
---. 1991. "Text Understanding -- A Self-organizing Cognitive
Process." Poetics 20: 273-301.
Searle, John R. 1974. Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy
of Language. London: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson. 1981. "Irony and the
Use-Mention Distinction." In Radical Pragmatics, edited
by Peter Cole, 295-318. London: Academic Press.
--- and ---. 1986. Relevance: Communication and Cognition.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Stanzel, Franz K. 1990. "Textual Power in the (Short) Short Story
and Poem." In Modes of Narrative: Approaches to American,
Canadian and British Fiction. Festschrift presented to Helmut
Bonheim, edited by Reingard M. Nischik and Barabara Korte, 20-30.
Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann.
Sternberg, Meir. 1978. Expositional Modes and Temporal
Ordering in Fiction. London: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press.
Todorov, Tzvetan. 1969. Grammaire du D‚cameron. Mouton:
The Hague.
---. 1981. Introduction to Poetics. Brighton:
Harvester.
Turner, Mark. 1996. The Literary Mind. Oxford: Oxford
Univ. Press.
Warhol, Robyn R. 1989. Gendered Interventions: Narrative
Discourse in the Victorian Novel. New Brunswick: Rutgers
Univ. Press.
---. 1999. "Forms, Feelings, Feminisms: What Feminist Narratology
Can Do for Cultural Studies". In Narratologies: New
Perspectives on Narrative Analysis, edited by David Herman.
Ohio: Ohio State Univ. Press.